Skip to content
Projects
Groups
Snippets
Help
Loading...
Help
Contribute to GitLab
Sign in
Toggle navigation
C
cpdt
Project
Project
Details
Activity
Cycle Analytics
Repository
Repository
Files
Commits
Branches
Tags
Contributors
Graph
Compare
Charts
Issues
0
Issues
0
List
Board
Labels
Milestones
Merge Requests
0
Merge Requests
0
CI / CD
CI / CD
Pipelines
Jobs
Schedules
Charts
Wiki
Wiki
Snippets
Snippets
Members
Members
Collapse sidebar
Close sidebar
Activity
Graph
Charts
Create a new issue
Jobs
Commits
Issue Boards
Open sidebar
research
cpdt
Commits
537fdfa9
Commit
537fdfa9
authored
Sep 27, 2008
by
Adam Chlipala
Browse files
Options
Browse Files
Download
Email Patches
Plain Diff
Propositional logic
parent
0b421721
Changes
3
Show whitespace changes
Inline
Side-by-side
Showing
3 changed files
with
212 additions
and
2 deletions
+212
-2
Makefile
Makefile
+1
-1
InductiveTypes.v
src/InductiveTypes.v
+1
-1
Predicates.v
src/Predicates.v
+210
-0
No files found.
Makefile
View file @
537fdfa9
MODULES_NODOC
:=
Tactics
MODULES_NODOC
:=
Tactics
MODULES_PROSE
:=
Intro
MODULES_PROSE
:=
Intro
MODULES_CODE
:=
StackMachine InductiveTypes
MODULES_CODE
:=
StackMachine InductiveTypes
Predicates
MODULES_DOC
:=
$(MODULES_PROSE)
$(MODULES_CODE)
MODULES_DOC
:=
$(MODULES_PROSE)
$(MODULES_CODE)
MODULES
:=
$(MODULES_NODOC)
$(MODULES_DOC)
MODULES
:=
$(MODULES_NODOC)
$(MODULES_DOC)
VS
:=
$
(
MODULES:%
=
src/%.v
)
VS
:=
$
(
MODULES:%
=
src/%.v
)
...
...
src/InductiveTypes.v
View file @
537fdfa9
...
@@ -18,7 +18,7 @@ Set Implicit Arguments.
...
@@ -18,7 +18,7 @@ Set Implicit Arguments.
(
**
%
\
chapter
{
Introducing
Inductive
Types
}%
*
)
(
**
%
\
chapter
{
Introducing
Inductive
Types
}%
*
)
(
**
In
a
sense
,
CIC
is
built
from
just
two
relatively
straightforward
features
:
function
types
and
inductive
types
.
From
this
modest
foundation
,
we
can
prove
effectively
all
of
the
theorems
of
math
and
carry
out
effectively
all
program
verifications
,
with
enough
effort
expended
.
This
chapter
introduces
induction
and
recursion
in
Coq
and
shares
some
"design patterns"
for
overcoming
common
pitfalls
with
them
.
*
)
(
**
In
a
sense
,
CIC
is
built
from
just
two
relatively
straightforward
features
:
function
types
and
inductive
types
.
From
this
modest
foundation
,
we
can
prove
effectively
all
of
the
theorems
of
math
and
carry
out
effectively
all
program
verifications
,
with
enough
effort
expended
.
This
chapter
introduces
induction
and
recursion
for
functional
programming
in
Coq
.
*
)
(
**
*
Enumerations
*
)
(
**
*
Enumerations
*
)
...
...
src/Predicates.v
0 → 100644
View file @
537fdfa9
(
*
Copyright
(
c
)
2008
,
Adam
Chlipala
*
*
This
work
is
licensed
under
a
*
Creative
Commons
Attribution
-
Noncommercial
-
No
Derivative
Works
3.0
*
Unported
License
.
*
The
license
text
is
available
at
:
*
http
:
//creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/
*
)
(
*
begin
hide
*
)
Require
Import
List
.
Require
Import
Tactics
.
Set
Implicit
Arguments
.
(
*
end
hide
*
)
(
**
%
\
chapter
{
Inductive
Predicates
}%
*
)
(
**
The
so
-
called
"Curry-Howard Correspondence"
states
a
formal
connection
between
functional
programs
and
mathematical
proofs
.
In
the
last
chapter
,
we
snuck
in
a
first
introduction
to
this
subject
in
Coq
.
Witness
the
close
similarity
between
the
types
[
unit
]
and
[
True
]
from
the
standard
library
:
*
)
Print
unit
.
(
**
[[
Inductive
unit
:
Set
:=
tt
:
unit
]]
*
)
Print
True
.
(
**
[[
Inductive
True
:
Prop
:=
I
:
True
]]
*
)
(
**
Recall
that
[
unit
]
is
the
type
with
only
one
value
,
and
[
True
]
is
the
proposition
that
always
holds
.
Despite
this
superficial
difference
between
the
two
concepts
,
in
both
cases
we
can
use
the
same
inductive
definition
mechanism
.
The
connection
goes
further
than
this
.
We
see
that
we
arrive
at
the
definition
of
[
True
]
by
replacing
[
unit
]
by
[
True
]
,
[
tt
]
by
[
I
]
,
and
[
Set
]
by
[
Prop
]
.
The
first
two
of
these
differences
are
superficial
changes
of
names
,
while
the
third
difference
is
the
crucial
one
for
separating
programs
from
proofs
.
A
term
[
T
]
of
type
[
Set
]
is
a
type
of
programs
,
and
a
term
of
type
[
T
]
is
a
program
.
A
term
[
T
]
of
type
[
Prop
]
is
a
logical
proposition
,
and
its
proofs
are
of
type
[
T
]
.
[
unit
]
has
one
value
,
[
tt
]
.
[
True
]
has
one
proof
,
[
I
]
.
Why
distinguish
between
these
two
types
?
Many
people
who
have
read
about
Curry
-
Howard
in
an
abstract
context
and
not
put
it
to
use
in
proof
engineering
answer
that
the
two
types
in
fact
%
\
textit
{%
#
<
i
>
#
should
not
#
</
i
>
#
%}%
be
distinguished
.
There
is
a
certain
aesthetic
appeal
to
this
point
of
view
,
but
I
want
to
argue
that
it
is
best
to
treat
Curry
-
Howard
very
loosely
in
practical
proving
.
There
are
Coq
-
specific
reasons
for
preferring
the
distinction
,
involving
efficient
compilation
and
avoidance
of
paradoxes
in
the
presence
of
classical
math
,
but
I
will
argue
that
there
is
a
more
general
principle
that
should
lead
us
to
avoid
conflating
programming
and
proving
.
The
essence
of
the
argument
is
roughly
this
:
to
an
engineer
,
not
all
functions
of
type
[
A
->
B
]
are
created
equal
,
but
all
proofs
of
a
proposition
[
P
->
Q
]
are
.
This
idea
is
known
as
%
\
textit
{%
#
<
i
>
#
proof
irrelevance
#
</
i
>
#
%}%,
and
its
formalizations
in
logics
prevent
us
from
distinguishing
between
alternate
proofs
of
the
same
proposition
.
Proof
irrelevance
is
compatible
with
,
but
not
derivable
in
,
Gallina
.
Apart
from
this
theoretical
concern
,
I
will
argue
that
it
is
most
effective
to
do
engineering
with
Coq
by
employing
different
techniques
for
programs
versus
proofs
.
Most
of
this
book
is
organized
around
that
distinction
,
describing
how
to
program
,
by
applying
standard
functional
programming
techniques
in
the
presence
of
dependent
types
;
and
how
to
prove
,
by
writing
custom
Ltac
decision
procedures
.
With
that
perspective
in
mind
,
this
chapter
is
sort
of
a
mirror
image
of
the
last
chapter
,
introducing
how
to
define
predicates
with
inductive
definitions
.
We
will
point
out
similarities
in
places
,
but
much
of
the
effective
Coq
user
'
s
bag
of
tricks
is
disjoint
for
predicates
versus
"datatypes."
This
chapter
is
also
a
covert
introduction
to
dependent
types
,
which
are
the
foundation
on
which
interesting
inductive
predicates
are
built
,
though
we
will
rely
on
tactics
to
build
dependently
-
typed
proof
terms
for
us
for
now
.
A
future
chapter
introduces
more
manual
application
of
dependent
types
.
*
)
(
**
*
Propositional
logic
*
)
(
**
Let
us
begin
with
a
brief
tour
through
the
definitions
of
the
connectives
for
propositional
logic
.
We
will
work
within
a
Coq
section
that
provides
us
with
a
set
of
propositional
variables
.
In
Coq
parlance
,
these
are
just
terms
of
type
[
Prop
.
]
*
)
Section
Propositional
.
Variables
P
Q
:
Prop
.
(
**
In
Coq
,
the
most
basic
propositional
connective
is
implication
,
written
[
->
]
,
which
we
have
already
used
in
almost
every
proof
.
Rather
than
being
defined
inductively
,
implication
is
built
into
Coq
as
the
function
type
constructor
.
We
have
also
already
seen
the
definition
of
[
True
]
.
For
a
demonstration
of
a
lower
-
level
way
of
establishing
proofs
of
inductive
predicates
,
we
turn
to
this
trivial
theorem
.
*
)
Theorem
obvious
:
True
.
apply
I
.
Qed
.
(
**
We
may
always
use
the
[
apply
]
tactic
to
take
a
proof
step
based
on
applying
a
particular
constructor
of
the
inductive
predicate
that
we
are
trying
to
establish
.
Sometimes
there
is
only
one
constructor
that
could
possibly
apply
,
in
which
case
a
shortcut
is
available
:
*
)
Theorem
obvious
'
:
True
.
constructor
.
Qed
.
(
**
There
is
also
a
predicate
[
False
]
,
which
is
the
Curry
-
Howard
mirror
image
of
[
Empty_set
]
from
the
last
chapter
.
*
)
Print
False
.
(
**
[[
Inductive
False
:
Prop
:=
]]
*
)
(
**
We
can
conclude
anything
from
[
False
]
,
doing
case
analysis
on
a
proof
of
[
False
]
in
the
same
way
we
might
do
case
analysis
on
,
say
,
a
natural
number
.
Since
there
are
no
cases
to
consider
,
any
such
case
analysis
succeeds
immediately
in
proving
the
goal
.
*
)
Theorem
False_imp
:
False
->
2
+
2
=
5.
destruct
1.
Qed
.
(
**
In
a
consistent
context
,
we
can
never
build
a
proof
of
[
False
]
.
In
inconsistent
contexts
that
appear
in
the
courses
of
proofs
,
it
is
usually
easiest
to
proceed
by
demonstrating
that
inconsistency
with
an
explicit
proof
of
[
False
]
.
*
)
Theorem
arith_neq
:
2
+
2
=
5
->
9
+
9
=
835.
intro
.
(
**
At
this
point
,
we
have
an
inconsistent
hypothesis
[
2
+
2
=
5
]
,
so
the
specific
conclusion
is
not
important
.
We
use
the
[
elimtype
]
tactic
to
state
a
proposition
,
telling
Coq
that
we
wish
to
construct
a
proof
of
the
new
proposition
and
then
prove
the
original
goal
by
case
analysis
on
the
structure
of
the
new
auxiliary
proof
.
Since
[
False
]
has
no
constructors
,
[
elimtype
False
]
simply
leaves
us
with
the
obligation
to
prove
[
False
]
.
*
)
elimtype
False
.
(
**
[[
H
:
2
+
2
=
5
============================
False
]]
*
)
(
**
For
now
,
we
will
leave
the
details
of
this
proof
about
arithmetic
to
[
crush
]
.
*
)
crush
.
Qed
.
(
**
A
related
notion
to
[
False
]
is
logical
negation
.
*
)
Print
not
.
(
**
[[
not
=
fun
A
:
Prop
=>
A
->
False
:
Prop
->
Prop
]]
*
)
(
**
We
see
that
[
not
]
is
just
shorthand
for
implication
of
[
False
]
.
We
can
use
that
fact
explicitly
in
proofs
.
The
syntax
[
~
P
]
expands
to
[
not
P
]
.
*
)
Theorem
arith_neq
'
:
~
(
2
+
2
=
5
)
.
unfold
not
.
(
**
[[
============================
2
+
2
=
5
->
False
]]
*
)
crush
.
Qed
.
(
**
We
also
have
conjunction
,
which
we
introduced
in
the
last
chapter
.
*
)
Print
and
.
(
**
[[
Inductive
and
(
A
:
Prop
)
(
B
:
Prop
)
:
Prop
:=
conj
:
A
->
B
->
A
/
\
B
]]
*
)
(
**
The
interested
reader
can
check
that
[
and
]
has
a
Curry
-
Howard
doppleganger
called
[
prod
]
,
the
type
of
pairs
.
However
,
it
is
generally
most
convenient
to
reason
about
conjunction
using
tactics
.
An
explicit
proof
of
commutativity
of
[
and
]
illustrates
the
usual
suspects
for
such
tasks
.
[
/
\
]
is
an
infix
shorthand
for
[
and
]
.
*
)
Theorem
and_comm
:
P
/
\
Q
->
Q
/
\
P
.
(
**
We
start
by
case
analysis
on
the
proof
of
[
P
/
\
Q
]
.
*
)
destruct
1.
(
**
[[
H
:
P
H0
:
Q
============================
Q
/
\
P
]]
*
)
(
**
Every
proof
of
a
conjunction
provides
proofs
for
both
conjuncts
,
so
we
get
a
single
subgoal
reflecting
that
.
We
can
proceed
by
splitting
this
subgoal
into
a
case
for
each
conjunct
of
[
Q
/
\
P
]
.
*
)
split
.
(
**
[[
2
subgoals
H
:
P
H0
:
Q
============================
Q
subgoal
2
is
:
P
]]
*
)
(
**
In
each
case
,
the
conclusion
is
among
our
hypotheses
,
so
the
[
assumption
]
tactic
finishes
the
process
.
*
)
assumption
.
assumption
.
Qed
.
(
**
Coq
disjunction
is
called
[
or
]
and
abbreviated
with
the
infix
operator
[
\
/
]
.
*
)
Print
or
.
(
**
[[
Inductive
or
(
A
:
Prop
)
(
B
:
Prop
)
:
Prop
:=
or_introl
:
A
->
A
\
/
B
|
or_intror
:
B
->
A
\
/
B
]]
*
)
(
**
We
see
that
there
are
two
ways
to
prove
a
disjunction
:
prove
the
first
disjunct
or
prove
the
second
.
The
Curry
-
Howard
analogue
of
this
is
the
Coq
[
sum
]
type
.
We
can
demonstrate
the
main
tactics
here
with
another
proof
of
commutativity
.
*
)
Theorem
or_comm
:
P
\
/
Q
->
Q
\
/
P
.
(
**
As
in
the
proof
for
[
and
]
,
we
begin
with
case
analysis
,
though
this
time
we
are
met
by
two
cases
instead
of
one
.
*
)
destruct
1.
(
**
[[
2
subgoals
H
:
P
============================
Q
\
/
P
subgoal
2
is
:
Q
\
/
P
]]
*
)
(
**
We
can
see
that
,
in
the
first
subgoal
,
we
want
to
prove
the
disjunction
by
proving
its
second
disjunct
.
The
[
right
]
tactic
telegraphs
this
intent
.
*
)
right
;
assumption
.
(
**
The
second
subgoal
has
a
symmetric
proof
.
[[
1
subgoal
H
:
Q
============================
Q
\
/
P
]]
*
)
left
;
assumption
.
Qed
.
End
Propositional
.
Write
Preview
Markdown
is supported
0%
Try again
or
attach a new file
Attach a file
Cancel
You are about to add
0
people
to the discussion. Proceed with caution.
Finish editing this message first!
Cancel
Please
register
or
sign in
to comment