Skip to content
Projects
Groups
Snippets
Help
Loading...
Help
Contribute to GitLab
Sign in
Toggle navigation
C
cpdt
Project
Project
Details
Activity
Cycle Analytics
Repository
Repository
Files
Commits
Branches
Tags
Contributors
Graph
Compare
Charts
Issues
0
Issues
0
List
Board
Labels
Milestones
Merge Requests
0
Merge Requests
0
CI / CD
CI / CD
Pipelines
Jobs
Schedules
Charts
Wiki
Wiki
Snippets
Snippets
Members
Members
Collapse sidebar
Close sidebar
Activity
Graph
Charts
Create a new issue
Jobs
Commits
Issue Boards
Open sidebar
research
cpdt
Commits
b0104b15
Commit
b0104b15
authored
Sep 28, 2008
by
Adam Chlipala
Browse files
Options
Browse Files
Download
Email Patches
Plain Diff
Recursive predicates
parent
c3665e97
Changes
2
Hide whitespace changes
Inline
Side-by-side
Showing
2 changed files
with
228 additions
and
1 deletion
+228
-1
Predicates.v
src/Predicates.v
+222
-0
Tactics.v
src/Tactics.v
+6
-1
No files found.
src/Predicates.v
View file @
b0104b15
...
...
@@ -440,3 +440,225 @@ Abort.
(
*
end
hide
*
)
(
**
*
Recursive
Predicates
*
)
(
**
We
have
already
seen
all
of
the
ingredients
we
need
to
build
interesting
recursive
predicates
,
like
this
predicate
capturing
even
-
ness
.
*
)
Inductive
even
:
nat
->
Prop
:=
|
EvenO
:
even
O
|
EvenSS
:
forall
n
,
even
n
->
even
(
S
(
S
n
))
.
(
**
Think
of
[
even
]
as
another
judgment
defined
by
natural
deduction
rules
.
[
EvenO
]
is
a
rule
with
nothing
above
the
line
and
[
even
O
]
below
the
line
,
and
[
EvenSS
]
is
a
rule
with
[
even
n
]
above
the
line
and
[
even
(
S
(
S
n
))]
below
.
The
proof
techniques
of
the
last
section
are
easily
adapted
.
*
)
Theorem
even_0
:
even
0.
constructor
.
Qed
.
Theorem
even_4
:
even
4.
constructor
;
constructor
;
constructor
.
Qed
.
(
**
It
is
not
hard
to
see
that
sequences
of
constructor
applications
like
the
above
can
get
tedious
.
We
can
avoid
them
using
Coq
'
s
hint
facility
.
*
)
Hint
Constructors
even
.
Theorem
even_4
'
:
even
4.
auto
.
Qed
.
Theorem
even_1_contra
:
even
1
->
False
.
inversion
1.
Qed
.
Theorem
even_3_contra
:
even
3
->
False
.
inversion
1.
(
**
[[
H
:
even
3
n
:
nat
H1
:
even
1
H0
:
n
=
1
============================
False
]]
*
)
(
**
[
inversion
]
can
be
a
little
overzealous
at
times
,
as
we
can
see
here
with
the
introduction
of
the
unused
variable
[
n
]
and
an
equality
hypothesis
about
it
.
For
more
complicated
predicates
,
though
,
adding
such
assumptions
is
critical
to
dealing
with
the
undecidability
of
general
inversion
.
*
)
inversion
H1
.
Qed
.
(
**
We
can
also
do
inductive
proofs
about
[
even
]
.
*
)
Theorem
even_plus
:
forall
n
m
,
even
n
->
even
m
->
even
(
n
+
m
)
.
(
**
It
seems
a
reasonable
first
choice
to
proceed
by
induction
on
[
n
]
.
*
)
induction
n
;
crush
.
(
**
[[
n
:
nat
IHn
:
forall
m
:
nat
,
even
n
->
even
m
->
even
(
n
+
m
)
m
:
nat
H
:
even
(
S
n
)
H0
:
even
m
============================
even
(
S
(
n
+
m
))
]]
*
)
(
**
We
will
need
to
use
the
hypotheses
[
H
]
and
[
H0
]
somehow
.
The
most
natural
choice
is
to
invert
[
H
]
.
*
)
inversion
H
.
(
**
[[
n
:
nat
IHn
:
forall
m
:
nat
,
even
n
->
even
m
->
even
(
n
+
m
)
m
:
nat
H
:
even
(
S
n
)
H0
:
even
m
n0
:
nat
H2
:
even
n0
H1
:
S
n0
=
n
============================
even
(
S
(
S
n0
+
m
))
]]
*
)
(
**
Simplifying
the
conclusion
brings
us
to
a
point
where
we
can
apply
a
constructor
.
*
)
simpl
.
(
**
[[
============================
even
(
S
(
S
(
n0
+
m
)))
]]
*
)
constructor
.
(
**
[[
============================
even
(
n0
+
m
)
]]
*
)
(
**
At
this
point
,
we
would
like
to
apply
the
inductive
hypothesis
,
which
is
:
*
)
(
**
[[
IHn
:
forall
m
:
nat
,
even
n
->
even
m
->
even
(
n
+
m
)
]]
*
)
(
**
Unfortunately
,
the
goal
mentions
[
n0
]
where
it
would
need
to
mention
[
n
]
to
match
[
IHn
]
.
We
could
keep
looking
for
a
way
to
finish
this
proof
from
here
,
but
it
turns
out
that
we
can
make
our
lives
much
easier
by
changing
our
basic
strategy
.
Instead
of
inducting
on
the
structure
of
[
n
]
,
we
should
induct
%
\
textit
{%
#
<
i
>
#
on
the
structure
of
one
of
the
[
even
]
proofs
#
</
i
>
#
%}%.
This
technique
is
commonly
called
%
\
textit
{%
#
<
i
>
#
rule
induction
#
</
i
>
#
%}%
in
programming
language
semantics
.
In
the
setting
of
Coq
,
we
have
already
seen
how
predicates
are
defined
using
the
same
inductive
type
mechanism
as
datatypes
,
so
the
fundamental
unity
of
rule
induction
with
"normal"
induction
is
apparent
.
*
)
Restart
.
induction
1.
(
**
[[
m
:
nat
============================
even
m
->
even
(
0
+
m
)
subgoal
2
is
:
even
m
->
even
(
S
(
S
n
)
+
m
)
]]
*
)
(
**
The
first
case
is
easily
discharged
by
[
crush
]
,
based
on
the
hint
we
added
earlier
to
try
the
constructors
of
[
even
]
.
*
)
crush
.
(
**
Now
we
focus
on
the
second
case
:
*
)
intro
.
(
**
[[
m
:
nat
n
:
nat
H
:
even
n
IHeven
:
even
m
->
even
(
n
+
m
)
H0
:
even
m
============================
even
(
S
(
S
n
)
+
m
)
]]
*
)
(
**
We
simplify
and
apply
a
constructor
,
as
in
our
last
proof
attempt
.
*
)
simpl
;
constructor
.
(
**
[[
============================
even
(
n
+
m
)
]]
*
)
(
**
Now
we
have
an
exact
match
with
our
inductive
hypothesis
,
and
the
remainder
of
the
proof
is
trivial
.
*
)
apply
IHeven
;
assumption
.
(
**
In
fact
,
[
crush
]
can
handle
all
of
the
details
of
the
proof
once
we
declare
the
induction
strategy
.
*
)
Restart
.
induction
1
;
crush
.
Qed
.
(
**
Induction
on
recursive
predicates
has
similar
pitfalls
to
those
we
encountered
with
inversion
in
the
last
section
.
*
)
Theorem
even_contra
:
forall
n
,
even
(
S
(
n
+
n
))
->
False
.
induction
1.
(
**
[[
n
:
nat
============================
False
subgoal
2
is
:
False
]]
*
)
(
**
We
are
already
sunk
trying
to
prove
the
first
subgoal
,
since
the
argument
to
[
even
]
was
replaced
by
a
fresh
variable
internally
.
This
time
,
we
find
it
easiest
to
prove
this
theorem
by
way
of
a
lemma
.
Instead
of
trusting
[
induction
]
to
replace
expressions
with
fresh
variables
,
we
do
it
ourselves
,
explicitly
adding
the
appropriate
equalities
as
new
assumptions
.
*
)
Abort
.
Lemma
even_contra
'
:
forall
n
'
,
even
n
'
->
forall
n
,
n
'
=
S
(
n
+
n
)
->
False
.
induction
1
;
crush
.
(
**
At
this
point
,
it
is
useful
to
consider
all
cases
of
[
n
]
and
[
n0
]
being
zero
or
nonzero
.
Only
one
of
these
cases
has
any
trickyness
to
it
.
*
)
destruct
n
;
destruct
n0
;
crush
.
(
**
[[
n
:
nat
H
:
even
(
S
n
)
IHeven
:
forall
n0
:
nat
,
S
n
=
S
(
n0
+
n0
)
->
False
n0
:
nat
H0
:
S
n
=
n0
+
S
n0
============================
False
]]
*
)
(
**
At
this
point
it
is
useful
to
use
a
theorem
from
the
standard
library
,
which
we
also
proved
with
a
different
name
in
the
last
chapter
.
*
)
Check
plus_n_Sm
.
(
**
[[
plus_n_Sm
:
forall
n
m
:
nat
,
S
(
n
+
m
)
=
n
+
S
m
]]
*
)
rewrite
<-
plus_n_Sm
in
H0
.
(
**
The
induction
hypothesis
lets
us
complete
the
proof
.
*
)
apply
IHeven
with
n0
;
assumption
.
(
**
As
usual
,
we
can
rewrite
the
proof
to
avoid
referencing
any
locally
-
generated
names
,
which
makes
our
proof
script
more
robust
to
changes
in
the
theorem
statement
.
*
)
Restart
.
Hint
Rewrite
<-
plus_n_Sm
:
cpdt
.
induction
1
;
crush
;
match
goal
with
|
[
H
:
S
?
N
=
?
N0
+
?
N0
|-
_
]
=>
destruct
N
;
destruct
N0
end
;
crush
;
eauto
.
Qed
.
(
**
We
write
the
proof
in
a
way
that
avoids
the
use
of
local
variable
or
hypothesis
names
,
using
the
[
match
]
tactic
form
to
do
pattern
-
matching
on
the
goal
.
We
use
unification
variables
prefixed
by
question
marks
in
the
pattern
,
and
we
take
advantage
of
the
possibility
to
mention
a
unification
variable
twice
in
one
pattern
,
to
enforce
equality
between
occurrences
.
The
hint
to
rewrite
with
[
plus_n_Sm
]
in
a
particular
direction
saves
us
from
having
to
figure
out
the
right
place
to
apply
that
theorem
,
and
we
also
take
critical
advantage
of
a
new
tactic
,
[
eauto
]
.
[
crush
]
uses
the
tactic
[
intuition
]
,
which
,
when
it
runs
out
of
tricks
to
try
using
only
propositional
logic
,
by
default
tries
the
tactic
[
auto
]
,
which
we
saw
in
an
earlier
example
.
[
auto
]
attempts
Prolog
-
style
logic
programming
,
searching
through
all
proof
trees
up
to
a
certain
depth
that
are
built
only
out
of
hints
that
have
been
registered
with
[
Hint
]
commands
.
Compared
to
Prolog
,
[
auto
]
places
an
important
restriction
:
it
never
introduces
new
unification
variables
during
search
.
That
is
,
every
time
a
rule
is
applied
during
proof
search
,
all
of
its
arguments
must
be
deducible
by
studying
the
form
of
the
goal
.
[
eauto
]
relaxes
this
restriction
,
at
the
cost
of
possibly
exponentially
greater
running
time
.
In
this
particular
case
,
we
know
that
[
eauto
]
has
only
a
small
space
of
proofs
to
search
,
so
it
makes
sense
to
run
it
.
It
is
common
in
effectively
-
automated
Coq
proofs
to
see
a
bag
of
standard
tactics
applied
to
pick
off
the
"easy"
subgoals
,
finishing
off
with
[
eauto
]
to
handle
the
tricky
parts
that
can
benefit
from
ad
-
hoc
exhaustive
search
.
The
original
theorem
now
follows
trivially
from
our
lemma
.
*
)
Theorem
even_contra
:
forall
n
,
even
(
S
(
n
+
n
))
->
False
.
intros
;
apply
even_contra
'
with
(
S
(
n
+
n
))
n
;
trivial
.
Qed
.
src/Tactics.v
View file @
b0104b15
...
...
@@ -12,6 +12,11 @@ Require Import List.
Require
Omega
.
Ltac
simplHyp
:=
match
goal
with
|
[
H
:
S
_
=
S
_
|-
_
]
=>
injection
H
;
clear
H
;
intros
;
subst
end
.
Ltac
rewriteHyp
:=
match
goal
with
|
[
H
:
_
|-
_
]
=>
rewrite
H
...
...
@@ -23,6 +28,6 @@ Ltac rewriter := autorewrite with cpdt in *; rewriterP.
Hint
Rewrite
app_ass
:
cpdt
.
Ltac
sintuition
:=
simpl
in
*;
intuition
.
Ltac
sintuition
:=
simpl
in
*;
intuition
;
try
simplHyp
.
Ltac
crush
:=
sintuition
;
rewriter
;
sintuition
;
try
omega
.
Write
Preview
Markdown
is supported
0%
Try again
or
attach a new file
Attach a file
Cancel
You are about to add
0
people
to the discussion. Proceed with caution.
Finish editing this message first!
Cancel
Please
register
or
sign in
to comment